Saturday, August 16, 2025

"Hey, if I found out somebody had been sneaking into my fitness club for years without paying, I'd want him arrested!"

 




The complaint encapsulated by the above title corresponds to the Republican Party's attitude toward "illegals" at present, and is now being tied to the current dispute over whether the U.S. Census should include the counting of non-citizens. Even when the critic of the current process concedes that "illegals" won't be allowed to vote--a concession which, of course, is  quite unlikely given who these particular critics are--based on the (unassailable) point that counting such individuals in the Census has effects on the distribution of Congressional and Electoral College seats, they are likely continue to maintain their objection to counting "illegals" in the Census.

Are such effects inappropriate, akin to letting a poacher dominate use of the gym eliptical (every freaking day!?) The short response is that countries are not clubs.  If a fitness establishment has rules requiring the payment of fees, then it is quite reasonable to insist that nobody should be getting club benefits without paying up. But territories are importantly different: if they are to be considered authentically democratic, they must have  authentically democratic rules and rule-making in place. The "benefits of citizenship" should not be thought to extend to voting rights in any real democracy, because the latter are required to ground citizenship there. That is, while votes should be taken to be the appropriate way to make almost every public policy--those that constitute and constrain democracy itself are exceptions to that rule

Without that crucial deviation, there could be no good objection to calling what Putin is attempting in Ukraine or Netanyahu would like to achieve in Gaza examples of forceful democritization of deviant territories. In other words, when a sufficiently powerful alien country takes over a territory, they can set forth a list of whose preferences are to be counted there, and so long as they hold events that look something like elections occasionally, they can describe what they have done as being consistent with "democratic nation building." 

Naturally, some individual or country might have the power to take this or that land (even planet!) by force; the point is that the immediate result of such conquest can never be correctly called the creation of a democratic polity unless every competent inhabitant there gets to vote on  all matters of national policy (again excluding axiomatic democratic principles).

The appropriate way to prevent an entire world of might makes right among those nations calling themselves "democracies" is to insist that once people have been living in a territory for a reasonable period of time--say a year--they must have an absolutely inviolable right to equal involvement in the determination of (nearly all) nearly all the public rules there. 

The equal effective electoral power of all competent residents# should extend even to policies involving immigration, emigration, and citizenship. The crucial exception, however, is that such policies (even those regarding citizenship or "wall-building") cannot extend to voting rights.

In other words, a group of people can make a club and put whatever rules in place for it that they want. But a group of conquerors can't just declare ownership of a populated area and imagine that it will be a democracy whoever they announce has the right to vote there. 

Getting back to our original question, this means that the fight regarding which individuals should be included in U.S. Census tallies must be determined in accordance with at least something like the Democratic Party's preferences, because if all competent residents--regardless of their "legal status"--aren't counted for the purpose of determining, e.g., the appropriate number of Congresspersons for each state, the U.S. cannot reasonably assert the right to be included among the democratic republics of the world.##

Other purposes of the Census, like those involving the distribution of Federal funds, aren't in the same category. The question of whether only citizens should be counted for the purpose of welfare determinations is something that, arguably SHOULD be subject to majority vote. The point is that all the non-temporary residents must be allowed to vote on them if any question of that sort is put to "the people." 

Authentic democracy absolutely requires that every long-term resident (even incarcerated felons) be treated equally with respect to the weights given their preferences, and it doesn't matter in the slightest how the majority of those who are currently eligible to vote in America would prefer this dispute to be resolved. No territory can remain a democratic polity if it allows for the undermining of basic democratic principles--even by its voters. Not only would a majority be insufficient to legitimately exclude non-citizens from being counted in any Census used to determine numbers of representatives, unanimous consent wouldn't do the trick either. 

This isn't actually that complicated if one thinks about what is necessary to make something a democracy and remembers that the democratic axioms landed upon cannot be abandoned without forsaking democracy itself.

----------

#For a brief discussion of "competence," see my blog entry for 9/14/23 and the one for 7/18/25. For discussions of "residence" and "inhabitancy, see my bookespecially Chapters 5 and 6.

##Admittedly, whether the US should now be (or should have ever been) included either way is a good question...but never mind that vexing matter for the present.

Tuesday, August 12, 2025

Arendt's Strange Take on Truths, Opinions and Facts

 


Hannah Arendt has certainly been having her day. That she led a fascinating--even romantic--life, is clear from several recent movies and documentaries about her. She wrote both knowedgeably and passionately on subjects that are of the utmost importance in the world today: totalitarianism, refugee problems, political reform movements, racism. She was both prolific and deep. Some of her work, particularly that which focused on what she called "the banality of evil"  touched a nerve and was extremely controversial. It is unsurprising, in view of the clearly authoritarian turn in U.S. governance these days that Arendt, who was something of an expert on both Nazism and Stalinism, has gotten extremely popular of late. (But maybe it's a little unexpected to find something he calls "Arendt's Law" in Paul Krugman's most recent Substack essay.#)

I am not an Arendt scholar myself. But, as I have been reading some of her work lately, partly as the result of a recent review of a book by Margaret Canovan (who was an Arendt scholar) and partly in anticipation of writing something on a new book on truth and politics by Michael Patrick Lynch, I thought I would try to give those unfamiliar with Arendt's work a sense of just how exotic her views on truth and opinion are. 

As far as I can tell, Arendt first discussed this matter publicly in a lecture on Truth and Politics that she delivered at Notre Dame University in 1954. Rather than take complete credit for her unconventional theory, she attributes its main outlines to an anti-Socratic strain in Plato's thought.## The idea is that Plato was as disgusted by the treatment of Socrates by city folk as a liberal reader of the New York Post or X today might be at MAGA-oriented comments found there. On Arendt's view, Plato felt that Socrates should have been understood to be above the common fray, to be engaged in the hunt for eternal truths, in spite of the polis attitude that, "If he's so much smarter than we are and has nothing to offer about how to make our lives better, why doesn't he at least write brilliant plays or poetry or make beautiful statues? In reality, the guy is good for nothing at all!"  

Now, according to Arendt, Socrates didn't agree with Plato that philosophy could not provide better lives for the people. For Plato took TRUTHs to be absolutely separate from the sort of facts that would ever be of interest to the people, while Socrates thought he could help make things better for the polis. According to Arendt's Plato, all the common folk can have are OPINIONs: they are as far from TRUTHs as cave dwellers are from the sun. Keep in mind that this failing isn't just a matter of how much evidence has been complied on behalf of some proposition or other, as if something could cease to be a mere opinion when justification for it reaches some level of sufficiency. Rather, an ontological separation is being made here between propositions of essentially different types. 

The idea here is that what is a mere OPINION can never reach the level of a TRUTH, no matter how much evidence for it is amassed. That's because, on this view, TRUTHs all resemble "2 +2 = 4" while OPINIONS are more along the lines of "Aristophanes tells a better story than Sophocles." So, it's claimed that there is a sort of objectivity to propositions of one group that can never be exemplified by propositions in the other category. And persuasion, while relevant to the world of OPINION, is simply out of place when we are talking about TRUTHs. So, on Plato's view (according to Arendt), Socrates was mostly wasting his time chatting up the people of Athens.

The oddness of this way of sorting propositions is that it is customary to attribute the property of being true or being false to beliefs, statements, propositions, etc., whatever the nature of their content. In ordinary language, we take the predicate "true" to mean exactly the same thing, whatever the content of the proposition to which it is being ascribed. It doesn't matter whether we are talking about an axiom of geometry or a description of a meal: we either get things right or we don't. What we say, write, or believe is either true or it isn't. (Though maybe, in the case of value judgments, like how good the meal tasted or how funny the comedian was, it might be neither, or at least the proposition might be said to be insufficiently specified.) 

But Arendt understood this matter quite differently. For her, OPINIONs can never be TRUE. On the other hand, she claims that one's OPINIONs are not exactly "subjective." They "comprehend the world as it opens itself" to one. Thus, although they don't reflect "subjective fantasy and arbitrariness," neither can they ever be understood as "something absolute and valid for all," and on this view, it is only that sort of universality which can make something TRUE. This is because, although "the world upens up differently to every man according to his position in it...the sameness of the world, its commonness or objectivity resides in the fact that the same world opens up to everyone and that despite all differences between men and their positions in the world...both you and I are human."

This appeal to intersubjectivity is a bit confusing (perhaps especially so to those like me who are not steeped in the "continental" side of modern philosophy). But, leaving complicated niceties aside, it is fairly easy to see a problem. Like many of us in today's AI-infested world, Arendt was  extremely concerned in her own time about the near omnipresence of lying. (She was particularly exercised by the Pentagon Papers.) She recognized that both those in power and those in search of it have, since the birth of politics, used untruths almost any time it was believed that deceptions would increase the liar's power or popularity. 

Now, there is no obvious tension between Arendt's conception of OPINION and the possibility of lying: one simply expresses something that does not jibe with how the "world has opened up." The problem emerges when one considers that (i) the things politicians lie about are usually neither "rational" TRUTHs nor doxa (OPINIONs), but contingent, often verifiable facts; and (ii) Arendt has no doubt whatever about the truth of a vast number of such propositions. In her 1967 New Yorker article "Truth and Politics," Arendt writes that "considerably more than the whims of historians would be needed to eliminate from the record the fact that on the night of August 4, 1914, German troops crossed the frontier of Belgium." And she adds that "Once perceived as true," statements like 'In August 1914 Germany invaded Belgium' "are beyond agreement, dispute, opinion, or consent." This is so, she says, because "for those who accept them, they are not changed by the numbers or lack of numbers who entertain the same proposition; persuasion or dissuasion is useless, for the content of the statement is not of a persuasive nature but of a coercive one....Facts are beyond agreement and consent, and all talk about them – all exchanges of opinion based on correct information – will contribute nothing to their establishment. Unwelcome opinion can be argued with, rejected, or compromised upon, but unwelcome facts possess an infuriating stubbornness that nothing can move except plain lies." When it comes to "brutally elementary data of this kind," Arendt tells us, "their indestructibility has been taken for granted even by the most extreme and most sophisticated believers in historicism."

Arendt's astonishment at the audacity of some liars brings her to absolute outrage: "Even if we admit that every generation has the right to write its own history, we admit no more than that it has the right to rearrange the facts in accordance with its own perspective; we don’t admit the right to touch the factual matter itself."

That may all be eminentally reasonable, but, unfortunately, it is inconsistent with Arendt's ontological categorization of TRUTHs vs. OPINIONs. The claim that Germany invaded Belgium in August 1914 is a simple contingent fact on her view: i.e., neither a (rational/philosophical) TRUTH nor an OPINION (i.e., an example of doxa).### 

The moral here, I think, is that the concept of truth is, as thinkers as diverse as Aristotle and Tarski have pointed out, singular and absolutely fundamental. There isn't one kind for philosophers and another kind for Fox News viewers...or one kind for algebra and another for The New Yorker. But it confuses things to suggest that contingent matters of fact are "beyond agreement, dispute, opinion or consent." It actually makes no difference whether something is completely obvious, highly controversial, or completely unknown, and it is contrary to coherence to bring in epistemological matters here: propositions are either true or they aren't--whatever our relation to them may happen to be.

------


#His piece. In case you're wondering, Krugman defines "Arendt's Law" as Totalitarian and wannabe totalitarian regimes only hire incompetent hacks.

##I want to stress the fact that in addition to not being an expert on Arendt, I am also very far from being a Plato scholar. In fact, IIRC, I did not take a single course in Ancient Greek Philosophy either as an undergraduate or while in grad school. And I've never taught anything related to Platonic thought except a couple of well-known Dialogues in a class on Introduction to Ethics. I hope this will excuse my unwillingness to comment on the accuracy of Arendt's interpretations of Socrates, Plato, or Aristotle.

###For a more detailed discussion of this aspect of Arendt's work, I recommend John Nelson's "Politics and Truth," published in American Journal of Political Science (1978).



Thursday, July 31, 2025

Even the Best Works are Sometimes Followed by Mediocre Sequels




Back in 2014, Maria Paula Saffon and Nadia Urbinati published a paper in the journal Political Theory entitled "Procedural Democracy, the Bulwark of Equal Liberty." It's a brilliant article whose contemplation these days gives me some pain, because, while I indicated my indebtedness to Urbinati in a number of places in my 2020 book on democratic theory, I had never seen that particular piece. That stings because the authors not only make a particularly fine case for bringing Hans Kelsen's unmatched justification of democracy to the attention of 21st Century theorists, but also because of the lovely way in which they bash the heads together of (i) epistemic democrats, (ii) advocates of (a certain type of) populism, and (iii) minimalist Schumpeterians as if those alternative theorists were Larry, Moe, and Curly pretending to give a joint talk at an APA convention. [KLONK!]

Saffon and Urbinati defend a position they call "Procedural Democracy" or "Proceduralism," a view that seems to me absolutely right insofar as it stresses the intrinsic value of self-government and pounds home the fact that all the theorists they criticise fail to demonstrate a real grasp of the fact that without a functioning democracy in place it's almost absurd to consider a polity free. Their Proceduralism, which they claim to have largely derived from Kelsen (as well as Norberto Bobbio), never stirs far from the essential point that the freedom and equality of a citizenry cannot be maintained without an adequately functioning democracy.*

Taking these opposing positions in turn, what do Saffon and Urbinati say caused those who defend epistemic democracy (e.g., David Estlund and Helene Landemore) to have entirely missed the main plot of the rise of democracy over the last couple of hundred years? According to the authors, their main mistake was to understand the value of democracy to be entirely extrinsic, a way for a group to produce the most desirable outcomes. This misses majoritarianism's essential contribution to liberty. In addition, they point out that if policy instrumentality really were the main point of having democratic governments, every outcome that is worse than might have been produced by a (either beneficent or confused) despot is a good argument against democratic rule.

I heartily agree with everything in this portion of the Saffon/Urbinati critique. In fact, I made many of the same points in this recent paper (but, you know, like a decade later....)

The authors also do a good job on populists, but only if you restrict "Populism" in such a way that it refers exclusively to particularly disgusting variants of what I believe is actually a fairly wide variety of theories.** Clearly, a Schmittian style fascism is inconsistent with representative democracy, and if that's what populism is or must become, it's silly to call a populist entity democratic.

Now, I'm not suggesting that it's absurd to claim that populism has a fascistic streak. Its forms of "radical democracy" often prefer identification with leaders to more traditional representation. And, of course, if the Leader just IS us, it doesn't make much sense to disagree with him/her. Thus, any desire for pluralism and minority voice in government is commonly cast aside by populist regimes as being detrimental to the real people, the sort of thing that can only be wanted by harmful "elites." Saffon and Urbinati accuse populist sympathizer Ernesto Laclau of that attitude, in spite of conceding his goal of combining "homogeneity (the project of unifying different citizens) with heterogeneity (allowing their plurality of interests to be voiced)." This is because they take several of Laclau's remarks to be antithetical to pluralism. Consider this one: "The classical theory of political representation, reduces the people to a pluralism of interests and values, because it makes of power an empty place occupied by formal rules of the game."

Perhaps they're right. But that attitude certainly does not comport with that of American populists like W.S. U'Ren, who worked tirelessly over a period of many years to give additional voice in government to various minorities. Whatever. I don't want to quibble about the definition of "populism" here. If we take the term to refer exclusively to Schmittian/Trumpian conceptions of government rule as Saffon and Urbinati do, it's hard to deny that Populism will turn out to be anti-democratic to its core.

Interestingly, the authors point out that in its way fascist-leaning populism is akin to epistemic democracy: both are focused on a single feature that is extrinsic to democracy proper, and thus ignore democracy's intrinsic capacity to increase the equal freedom of a populace. The relevant difference between the two theories is that for Populists, it is the unified and unstoppable "power of the people" rather than truth that is the holy grail.

Saffon and Urbinati contrast their rule-centric Proceduralism with one more general democratic theory here: a position they call "Minimalism," (or sometimes "Realism"), a theory that they say originated with Joseph Schumpeter. That position is minimalist in the sense that it calls for only that amount of democracy--and no more--that will prevent a system from being correctly identifiable as either anarchic or despotic. Minimalism is, as Przeworski indicates, basically a way to "get rid of governments without bloodshed," whether or not such governments make any attempt to figure out what the citizenry actually wants. In this way, it could be argued that Minimalism need only fool a populace into abandoning violence in favor of occasional elections that do nothing at all substantive in the area of policy choice. In addition, the Minimalist conception is said to "disregard equality as a key dimension of democracy."

Thus, by Minimalist lights, a little discrimination against this or that group is OK so long as the "rules of the game" are sufficiently kept to ensure that power can be transferred peacefully. In its fear (and arguably also loathing) of the masses, it generally allows no governmental power to be distributed to citizens other than the right to vote for one or more representatives occasionally. Obviously, however, having an election every so often isn't sufficient to produce a democratic polity, particularly if it's OK if these plebiscites are nothing but ruses.***

According to Saffon and Urbinati, the conclusion to draw from the defects of each of these alternatives to Proceduralism is that where authentic citizen preferences for this or that action, policy, and representative are downplayed--or even ignored, so will be the freedom of that populace to choose its own future.

So, in spite of a bit of hand-waving about what seems to me the intractable tension between majoritarian democracy and the problem of persistent minorities, this 2014 paper seems to me to have been a vital contribution to political theory, the sort of article that is sure to have made fans look forward to a sequel. And, within the last month or so, a follow-up paper called "Parties as Agents of Equal Freedom" did appear in the same journal. But, alas, as with so many sequels to excellent creations....

-----

While the place of political parties was not a highly visable feature of the earlier work, the new paper is focused on the claimed indispensibility of parties to any functioning democracy. However, the authors don't try to hide the fact that historically parties have often been less than virtuous. They write, in fact, "Parties have often turned into oligarchic structures disconnected from their bases." "They have also frequently become cartels who [sic] live off the state, protect vested interests, and engage in collusive practices," and note that they are "increasingly immoderate in their opinions and practices, stretching the democratic rules of the game." Saffon and Urbinati nevertheless mostly attend to the positive aspects of political parties, partly because they don't believe it's possible for democracies to amount to much without their crucial contributions to pluralist thought.

Thus, while Saffon and Urbinati maintain that parties are necessary to democracy and at least can be healthy supplements to sound democratic practices, their affection extends only to the good kind of parties, not, e.g., National Socialism or Trumpian Republicanism. That makes sense, of course, but rather than extend this quite reasonable attitude to advocates of non-Procedural democratic theories, they claim that Populists, Minimalists, and "Epistemics"# are antithetical to parties no matter how the latter institutions happen to be constituted or act in actual practice.

[Chart by a Reddit contributor with the moniker Mgmfjesus]


Unfortunately, the conclusions of the critique here are almost entirely predestined by the paradigms they choose for each of their adversaries. We have already seen this with respect to Populism in the first article, when they chose Schmitt as its primary spokesperson. I mean, to take a couple of the most famous Schmittian Populists, both Hitler and Mussolini were quite explicit that there should only be ONE political party. So, if "Populist" is a term for those sorts of positions only, it's pretty clear that there will not be a place for any parties but the single good one. Fascism is simply incompatible with pluralistic democracy of any kind.

In the sequel paper, this same kind of distortive conceit is applied to epistemic democracy, when, instead of Condorcet, they use Rousseau as the original model for that theory. And to make things worse, they imply that epistemic democracy is essentially tied up with deliberationism. Now, it can't be denied that several epistemic democrats (e.g., Elizabeth Anderson and Helene Landemore) have stressed the importance of deliberation in their writings, and that view has also contributed to their hostility to parties. But it also should be clear that the two ideas of deliberative and epistemic democracy are entirely separable. The point of epistemic democracy is that voting is the best way to determine "correct public policies." A primary focus on deliberation is consistent with having no elections at all. While deliberation may be useful in the determination of what proposed policies an epistemic democrat thinks ought to be voted on, jury theorems do not depend on that detail. The two independent theories seem to me to have been conflated here for the sole purpose of insisting that epistemic democracy must be hostile to political parties. Furthermore, Anderson and Landemore notwithstanding, it's not obvious to me that even stand-alone deliberationism must be incompatible with strong parties: it will continue to depend on how the parties operate.##

It is also worth noting that several well-known exponents of epistemic democracy have not taken the position Saffon and Urbinati have set aside for them. Estlund has said almost nothing about this matter, Thomas Christiano, while sometimes antagonistic to parties (particularly when they display features that Saffon and Urbinati also criticize), has pushed for proportional representation, something that is generally considered dependent on a system that includes at least two parties. And for his part, Robert Talisse has mostly been focused of late on expressing the same sorts of concerns about the hyper-polarization of contemporary parties### that Saffon and Urbinati do in their paper.

Again, this misconstrual is not surprising: it's true that Rousseau may not have seen any need for political parties in determining the "general will," but he was not an epistemic democrat at all. And, again, deliberation is neither here nor there in this fight. In fact, although some deliberationists have been epistemic democrats (and vice-versa), it probably would have made more sense to make an additional place for deliberation-focused theorists rather than just lumping them with "Epistemics."

Turning finally to Minimalists, we may take Schumpeter and Riker as our guides. And we will find that, largely because of their dismissive attitude toward general electorates, they both saw parties as indispensible to democracy, even if more along the lines of necessary evils than as anything to get excited about. And it should be remembered that even an "evil" (the party system) that is necessary for something that is itself taken to be a necessary evil (plebiscitary democracy) should be understood to be a "positive influence," rather than, as our authors put it, nothing but "factions that devour the common good." In other words, if democracy is (even reluctantly) considered a good, and parties are necessary to it as Schumpeter and Riker clearly believed, parties are themselves good things. These Minimalists were quite clear about why they thought parties were essential. The sole purpose of democracy on their view is to retain the ability of a population to throw one group out and replace them with another. And for them, it is only parties that can outline the alternative batch of these alternating ne'er do wells in a manner that can be grasped by the plebes.(Przeworski's attitude is along the same lines.)

Now, I don't want to imply that there is nothing worthwhile in this article. There are, in fact, a good many useful recommendations regarding how contemporary parties should be run. And it may be a valuable piece if taken simply as a paeon to the importance of political parties for democratic polities. Indeed the work makes a number of important points along those lines, points which are, no doubt, regularly ignored by political theorists.

But the paper should not have contained the suggestion that either Minimalism, Epistemic Democracy, or Populism (as correctly understood) are necessarily antithetical to parties. There are, certainly, difficult problems to consider when attempting to make parties (and federal structures as well!) consistent with majoritarianism. But that perhaps unpleasant fact is largely an entailment of simple mathematics, and does not have to be connected with any disdain for pluralism. Certainly, those types of thorny problems connected with voting and elections need have nothing whatever to do with the sort of democratic theory one happens to prefer.

------------------------------

*While I also discuss Kelsen's importance to democratic theory in my book, I put more weight on the (likely less-well-known) work of Everett Hall in my provision of a somewhat similar justification for majority rule. Like the Kelsen/Urbinati/Saffon take, the Hall/Horn version also focuses on the intrinsic value of free choices in accordance with principles that I take to be foundational regarding the equal weight assignable to both persons and their wishes. 

**For a more comprehensive approach to populism I recommend both of Margaret Canovan's books on the subject. See also this paper, and/or my reviews of Canovan's The People and the Elgar Handbook on Populism here

***I wrote a bit about "fake elections" here.

#I admit that their frequent use of "the Epistemics" in this paper sometimes caused me to wonder whether they were referring to an 80's boy band or a group of ESP-powered arch rivals to Professor X.

##The soup gets even murkier when the authors mix in sortionism as though it too were intimately connected with either deliberation or epistemic democracy or both.

###See my review of one of his recent books.


Friday, July 25, 2025

Yet Another Conception of "Wasted Vote"

 




Back in March of 2024, I wrote a piece about the ambiguity of the term "wasted votes." In it I reproduced three or four inconsistent meanings of the expression that can be found around the web and are used by advocates for various reforms. But after reading Steven Hill's useful 2023 Substack essay, "Which Proportional Representation Method is Best for America?" I see that I left out an important conception of the term, one that Hill relies on extensively as a reason for preferring Ranked Choice Voting ["RCV"] to several popular Proportional Representation ["PR"] alternatives. 

While Hill doesn't actually define "wasted vote" in that piece, it is fairly easy to infer that he takes a vote to be wasted just in case it produces zero representation or voice for the voter who cast it. So, for example in an election for President or Senator in our winner-take-all system, if you voted for any losing candidate, Hill considers that to be a wasted vote. Where there is PR on the other hand, it is possible to vote for a second- (or third- or fourth-) place candidate and still get representation or voice. So, according to this conception, when that happens the votes are not wasted. 

That particular understanding of waste is somewhat different from each of the publicly available explanations I considered in my blog last year, including the definition that FairVote, an organization with which I believe Hill is closely associated, provides (or at least at one time provided) on its website; but it can't be denied that Hill's version has an intuitive, even  somewhat comforting, ring to it. I mean, one really might sensibly think I guess I could just as well have stayed home if it turns out that, subsequent to the next swearing-in ceremony, nobody will be representing one's views in the legislature, or council, or whatever. 

I think there are a couple of problems, however. First, it seems to me that it actually does make a difference whether a candidate wins by 30% or .02% of the vote. That is, the votes for losing candidates do matter in some sense, so long as they are counted and publicly published. Since close elections may constrain winners, it may be better to vote for a loser than stay home. So it could be reasonably concluded that such votes aren't really wasted.

Nevertheless, votes for losing candidates do seem wasted in SOME sense: what does the voter get for it? The problem is that if we consider RCV, Hill's favored way to reduce wastage, it seems wrong to infer that, so long as Smith has ranked Crawford at all, and Crawford wins a seat, that Crawford should be thought to be providing a "voice" for Smith. For example, I may prefer Vance to Trump--and may have strategic reasons for ranking Vance at all--but one can't reasonably infer from this that I want Vance, or that he will be speaking for me should he get elected. 

The idea that every ranking is a wanting is simply a problem for all ordinal voting methods: not even a top-ranking should automatically be thought to be a wanting. This is one reason that I believe Approval Voting ["AV"] is superior to every ordinal method in the search for proportionality--or at least would be if we could depend on voters to faithfully follow AV rules and vote for all and only those candidates of whom they actually approve. (Please note that I acknowledge with regret that voters may very well not follow those rules. See this article.) 

In fact, Hill's conception basically makes the determination of whether or not a vote is wasted depend on something that might be entirely extraneous to who one takes to be an appropriate representer of one's views. 

Take this cuckoo example. Suppose there is a PR voting rule that says "Put a mark next to all those candidates you have heard of, making the size of the mark bigger based on how frequently you have heard of him/her. If you have heard of this candidate a LOT, make a very large mark, and if you have only heard of him/her very infrequently (or you think you've heard of him/her but aren't entirely sure whether you've heard of him/her at all), make your mark very small. The votes are to be tallied as follows: the size of all marks made are to be "added up" and the five candidates producing the largest aggregated mark are to be declared winners. 

Under this rule and Hill's definition of "waste," a ballot will be wasted only if it includes no vote cast for a candidate among those who amass one of the five biggest splotches. In other words, in this scenario, those who voted only for candidates that most people hadn't heard much about would be considered to have wasted their votes, but those who cast ballots that included a smudge for any of the five best known candidates would NOT be wasting their votes. Obviously, that produces a very odd and unacceptable conception of voice.

Now, I am not suggesting that under RCV the rule requiring the ranking of candidates by how one compares them to others running for the same office should be considered tantamount to the crazy voting rule specified above. But I do think that if wasting a vote is thought to be a matter of not getting ones "voice" heard in the future chorus of representatives, a vote must be a matter of APPROVING a candidate as being someone one believes to be fit for the job, someone who is better than nothing; not just a matter of whether one likes him/her a bit more than some alternative considered to be almost equally awful.

Friday, July 18, 2025

A Drop of Good News Falls From the Pervasive Dark Clouds of Doom!

 



Something good has actually happened for the future of democracy someplace! Not in the U.S., natch, but in the land of Viginia Woolf and Thomas Hobbes. You know, our (one-time) close ally, England. Those hiding in their American basements between their meat freezers and their dart boards may wonder what it is that I believe ought have their populace absolutely chuffed. So, I will keep them in suspense no longer: ENGLAND HAVE/HAS LOWERED THE VOTING AGE IN NATIONAL ELECTIONS TO 16! 

There will, no doubt, be those who doubt that  this is really a good thing. In fact, the U.S. is home to a burgeoning new movement that advocates for the removal of suffrage from women (or, I suppose, those assigned Female at birth, or conception, or whatever this group thinks is the Godly way to put this sought after restriction). What those concerned gentlemen (mostly gents, anyhow) are quite sure of is that women don't "have what it takes" to be allowed to make a difference in their country based on their views--unless any difference-making opportunity they're given consists solely in begging their husbands, and that is something for which I think it's deemed OK by this group to beat them.

Now, of course, the proportion of the U.S. population that denies that 16- and 17-year olds have the mysterious something required to be eligible for voting rights is considerably larger than the fringe group that would remove women's suffrage. Indeed, the anti-youth vote segment even contains multitudes of women! It's not a marginal group at all. It's just those people who can be heard to say, "Teens simply aren't ready. I mean, have you ever talked to one? Let me get Bracey away from his screens for a minute and you'll see what I mean!"

These sorts of pronouncements aren't new: "They don't pay taxes! They don't know anything! They can't buy a rifle or get a mortgage! They never work! They don't care about anything but video games, halter top styles, muffin recipes, fantasy football or porn! For heaven's sake, if you think about this even for a minute, you'll see that it's a ridiculous-- even disgusting--idea!"

Of course, the same charges have long been--and in numerous quarters still are--aimed at non-caucasions--regardless of gender. 

I discuss this matter at some length in Chapter 6 of my book on democratic theory (which if you haven't yet read in its entirety, tsk, tsk). However, I am so delighted at seeing this news about what's happening in the Parliamentary world of dear Bertie that I will provide an excerpt from that book here. [For those who are already sick of reading at this point, the bottom line is: midteens should be allowed to vote, and democracy is that much worse where this right is not granted.]

First, there are a few pages spent on discussing the numerous arguments that have been brought against teen voting for centuries. I omit them here, as well as any footnotes to what I will reproduce. The text continues as follows:

So, what should voters be able to do? According to Vivian Hamilton (2011, 53), “a minimally competent voting decision involves the appropriate application and coordination of various reasoning processes to make a choice that could be justified by a good reason.” This is because, on her view (2011, 52-62), the ability to cast a non-random vote requires minimal competence in all of the following:

• The ability to learn and retrieve information.

• The ability to form mental representations of information.

• At least some ability to reason inductively, deductively and analogically.

• The ability to apply and coordinate reasoned inferences to some goal, like the solving of a problem or the making of a decision.

Once there is agreement on these, settling on a minimum voting age is simply a matter of consulting the literature on the stages of psychological development. That is precisely what Hamilton does, with patience and care. I will not rehearse her generous summary of the research here, but simply report the absolutely decisive conclusion that, (i) prior to the mid-teens (i.e., 16 or thereabouts) there is, on average, arguably insufficient maturity to meet Hamilton’s criteria; and (ii) after the mid-teens, there is, on average, no development in those areas significant enough to be declared relevant.

This result will not be surprising to anyone who has adult children. That something dramatic happens during the high school years is quite obvious. Athletes begin to have 90 miles-per-hour fastballs, close in on Olympic records, even get notifications of interest from professional teams. Musicians, visual artists, and actors begin to give performances or create pieces that could be staged without embarrassment anywhere in the world. Writers begin to compose publishable works of poetry and prose. Mathematicians suddenly make progress on matters that have stumped the world since the beginning of time. Chess and video game players become masters. Actors start to show multiple levels of depth and nuance of expression. Comedians become funny in original ways. Of course, some kids develop earlier, and some are late bloomers. But those of us who have gone to plays, concerts, games, showings, etc. at our children’s high schools will know that an incredible change takes place among the rank and file there. Clearly, if what the people in some polity want is a strict function of what the individuals in it want, 16-year-olds must be allowed to express their desires and aversions in the same manner as older members of society.

Will the votes of 16-year-olds be independent, or will they just ape the votes of their parents or teachers? It really doesn’t matter: nobody’s vote is entirely independent of those around them. What about the danger of teens simply being instructed to cast their votes in a particular manner by those who feed and house them? The secret ballot is a wonderful protection against coercion of that type. Will they not care enough to vote, based on the belief—correct or incorrect—that most of the issues won’t affect them? That is entirely up to them. Electoral indifference also provides useful information about the state of the populace. (And if they are made to go to the polls against their will, they can always write in Rihanna, Payton Manning, Zippy the Pinhead, or one of the Mutant Ninja Turtles: no harm will have been done). 

Let us agree then to take a break from either mourning or protesting--or whatever you think is most called for in these desperate times--and celebrate this brave British revision of its electoral rules. The new youth vote in England is estimated to constitute only 2% of the total electorate, and the new voters will remain ineligible to hold office themselves. But, in spite of its limits nobody should deny that this is a wonderful moment for democracy in the world. May more soon follow!!


 

 

Friday, July 11, 2025

Democracy Criteria From the Woodstock Days

 



Back in 1968, Professor David Braybrooke published his book Three Tests for Democracy. Much of that work focuses on rights and welfare, but the final third proposes tests for whether a polity is a democracy based on whether "collective preferences" are satisfied there.

While the writing may seem a bit stilted to the modern reader--especially one with no extensive background in either analytic philosophy or welfare economics (I admit to briefly wondering whether Braybrooke's style might have benefitted from cutting down on what I imagine to have been a hefty diet of G.E. Moore)--the main idea is fairly commonsensical: criteria for democratic government must have "something to do with majority rule" As Braybrooke puts it, "Consider a community of sane adults for which a number of mutually exclusive policies P1, P2, P3....Pn have been proposed. Suppose that it is known that a majority of the members of the community prefer P3 to all of the other policies--i.e., it is known that with one vote each to cast [a majority] would would vote for P3. Nevertheless the policy adopted for the community is not P3, but P2....[A]dvocates of democracy would find this result objectionable....[I]t is a flagrantly undemocratic result."

Now, Braybridge doesn't suggest that that adoption of P2 in all such cases is sufficient to show that the group in question is a democracy. Other requirements must also be met. He proposes, in addition, an Adoption Condition, according to which the government in question must sincerely attempt to get P2 put into practice, and a Participation Condition, which looks into both who gets to vote, and who actually does so. For example, if only 5% of the eligible voters bother to cast ballots, and 95% of that cohort are from a minority class, gender, social class, geographic region, ethnicity or race, it will be doubtful that the majority is ruling just because it the polity is apparently functioning in accordance with the results of that election.

I bring this 60s sentiment up because there is an awful lot of gnashing of teeth these days due to a fear that the loss of 'our democracy' is imminent. This keening can be heard on both the left (because of the alleged increase in fascist tendencies among Republicans) and on the right (because of an alleged increased reliance on "fake voters" and other types of election fraud by Democrats). 

Well, whoever may be right about what's happening in the country these days (and I hope my own views about this are known to my readers), it's pretty obvious that to lose something, you first must have it. Set aside for the moment the problems produced for U.S. democracy by the Electoral College, the Senate (and its Filibuster), the effects of gerrymandering, and all the other well-known defects in the American governmental structure. In a recent Substack piece, Lee Drutman displays in broad, dark strokes something particularly depressing about the U.S.: wealthy people are much more likely to vote here than poorer people are.


Drutman's fine piece can be read in its entirety here.

But, of course, that distressing piece of news just provides a bit of the causal story behind what we already ought to have known to be true: quite substantial majorities in the U.S. are simply not getting most of what they are known to want. As I mentioned on page 30 of my 2020 book on democratic theory, a now classic study of this issue, [Gilens and Page (2014)] "looked at about 1,800 policy positions considered by Congress between 1981 and 2002, and found that the views of the majority of Americans on those issues were largely ignored in favor of the the views espoused by powerful (mostly corporate) lobbyists." 

This situation has not improved since 2002. According to the most recent credible polling, substantial majorities are not getting what they want in such areas as gun control, abortion rights, climate change policy, marijuana legalization, student debt, and healthcare coverage. There is no doubt that we are far from a passing grade on Braybrooke's test here.

In a word, all this mournful talk about "losing our precious democracy" is a little nonsensical--whether we're hearing it on MSNBC or FOX. A facade is crumbling: that's all. Furthermore, in my own view, the widespread grief over this loss of something we never had is part and parcel of the blanket disparagement of "populism" as a political theory always to be feared. What IS indisputably bad is autocracy, but, in reality, whether or not it has entirely descended into some sort of fascist tyranny, autocratic rule is the very opposite of (any appropriately "distilled") populism, for the latter insists that democracy must be real, rather than merely imagined--with or without any accompanying flag.



Wednesday, July 9, 2025

A Few Key Quotes From Robert Jones's Book on White Supremacy



The Hidden Roots of White Supremacy | Book by Robert P. Jones | Official  Publisher Page | Simon & Schuster

In his excellent book on the history of American racial domination and genocide, Robert Jones focuses on "The Doctrine of Discovery," according to which it is always perfectly acceptable--indeed, required--for civilized, Christian (i.e., white, European) peoples to wrest land from darker savages--whether that latter group were already long established somewhere (like the indigenous people living in North America or Australia) or  arrived later--whether brought against their will like black slaves from Africa, or came voluntarily, like current immigrants from Mexico or Haiti. 

Jones puts the date at which he takes the The Doctrine of Discovery to have become the foundational principle of the future United States of America at 1493, but notes that its official enshrinement into legality here was accomplished by Chief Justice Marshall in a 33-page decision on the 1823 case of Johnson v. M'Intosh. Marshall there opined that 

[The rights of the Indians to sovereignty as independent nationswere necessarily diminished, and their power to dispose of the soil at their own will, to whomsoever they pleased, was denied by the original fundamental principle that discovery gave exclusive title to those who made it. 

While the different nations of Europe respected the right of the natives, as occupants, they asserted the ultimate dominion to be in themselves; and claimed and exercised, as a consequence of this ultimate dominion, a power to grant the soil, while yet in possession of the natives.

The Chief Justice seemed a little embarassed by this proclamation when he also noted in his opinion that, 

The potentates of the old world found no difficulty in convincing themselves that they made ample compensation to the inhabitants of the new, by bestowing on them civilization and Christianity, in exchange [for giving up their] unlimited independence.

But Marshall himself didn't rely on any exchange  being made here, fair or not. In his view, precedence was enough. Might has always simply made right.


Book Review: 'The Hidden Roots of White Supremacy,' by Robert P. Jones - The  New York Times


Unlike Marshall, Jones, a Ph.D. in religion and a graduate of the Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary, remains troubled by the Christian  background of these power grabs. Jones has not been alone in that sentiment. In fact, his book provides this excerpt from a 1955 sermon given in Montgomery, Alabama by the 26-year old Rev. Martin Luther King:

The white men who lynch Negroes worship Christ. That jury in Mississippi, which a few days ago in the Emmett Till case, freed two white men from what might be considered one of the most brutal and inhuman crimes of the twentieth century, worships Christ. The trouble is that all people, like the Pharisee, go to church regularly, they pay their tithes and offerings, and observe religiously the various cermonial requirements. The trouble with these people, however, is that they worship Christ emotionally and not morally. They cast his ethical and moral insights behind the gushing smoke of emotional adoration and ceremonial piety,

I get what King is saying here, but I'm not sure he was focused on quite the central problem. 

I see the use of Christianity in this context as being not very different from the employment of a claimed love of democracy as being a key reason for rapacious activities. Both are absolutely absurd. As Jones tells us, in the few weeks after a particularly disgusting display of violence in the Mississippi counties of Warren and Hinds in which white mobs killed 50 black Americans, including children and a state senator, taking over the of levers of "democracy" became the goal of the supremacists. 

"[W]hites engaged in a broad effort to rig the elections, including vigilante violence, voter intimidation, bribery of election officials and ballot tampering." Many blacks were hiding in the woods on the next election day. In fact, in one key county in which, thanks to  Reconstruction, blacks had briefly done well, only seven Republican ballots were counted as compared to 4,000 Democratic ballots. Naturally, once in power, the white minority did all they could to impeach any remaining black office-holders. These acts may have been proclaimed to be "redemption" by the self-described pious  Christian whites in Mississippi, but they weren't actually connected with anything in the Bible, or even with the Doctrine of Discovery. Supremacists have long touted religion or democracy (or whatever else they thought might help) when useful, but their actions have always been about getting their money, power, and self-respect back. And, of course, about simple hatred and fear of "the other."

If Jesus had specifically preached against any such domination principle as the Doctrine of Discovery (and I presume that many scholars would say he did!), it would have made no difference at all to those conducting their  lynching parties on their way to watch baseball games. Their "faith" has been no more important than their "patriotism" or "love of democracy" as  inducements to their appalling activities. It has been their cotton revenues, their exclusive right to hold public office, their position as kingpins, and their feelings of repulsion that have always been the significant incitements.

AMERICAN EXPERIENCE: The Murder Of Emmett Till | KPBS Public Media

Well, what about now? Same deal. Any spiel about the deep Christianity woven into some "nationalistic" movement is as phony as current Republican claims of a desire to "save our democracy" by such methods as stringent voter ID requirements. I.F. Stone made what was going on perfectly explicit as long ago as the Emmett Till trial when he wrote, 

The South must become either truly democratic or the base of a new racist and Fascist movement which could threaten the whole country and its institutions. 

Stone saw where we were heading back in the 1950s, and it was not toward anything that can correctly be called "Populism," which is a type of authentic, if arguably radical, democracy. It was in exactly the opposite direction.


Sunday, July 6, 2025

Jane Austen on the Difference Between Moral and Prudential Values



For at least a decade, I have been trying to get more respect for prudential values (that which is good for individuals and groups), based on the view that they have been badly mistreated by philosophers who seem to care only about what is morally right or good. I take up that cudgel once again in my latest book review, that of Bas van der Vossen's Political Philosophy: The Basics. In that piece I complain that theorists are all too prone to worry about what makes a state or a law legitimate, without much care about what makes that state or law good for the people who are subject to it.

But I feel myself chastised! Near the end of her novel Mansfield Park, Jane Austen spends perhaps the longest time she ever devoted to a philosophical problem, on having the somewhat priggish cleric Edmund Bertram castigate (his then crush) Mary Crawford for making prudential values not just first, but only! That is, Mary is discovered by him to have been absolutely incapable of distinguishing between the two sorts of value. When Edmund finally comes to realize her blindness--something the book's heroine Fanny Price had understood for some time--the both devastated and astonished lover is able to get over his feelings for Mary and (finally!) attach them to (the also somewhat priggish) Fanny. 



It's a brilliant multi-page passage. Edmund gives a detailed account to Fanny of his final talk with Mary, in this way trying to explain how Mary has fallen from his grace. 

Fanny suggests that Mary has been cruel. But Edmund demurs. "Cruelty do you call it? We differ there. No, hers is not a cruel nature. I do not consider her as meaning to wound my feelings. The evil lies yet deeper: in her total ignorance, unsuspiciousness of there being such feelings....Hers are faults of principle, Fanny; of blunted delicacy and a corrupted, vitiated mind." 

Edmund tries to make this clearer by explaining the way Mary treated the "dreadful crime committed by her brother and my sister [running off together, in spite of Edmund's sister's recent marriage to another man]....giving it every reproach but the right; considering its ill consequences only as they were to be braved or overborne by a defiance of decency and impudence in wrong; and...recommending to us a compliance, a compromise, an acquiescence in the continuance of the sin on the chance of a marriage." Mary did admit that the affair had been handled badly, but her thought was that whatever could now be done to mitigate the damage was in order. In her view, the whole kerfluffle might have been avoided if her brother had first married someone else for whom he apparently had feelings (Fanny). This would have been much better, Mary felt, because she believed it "would have all ended in a regular standing flirtation, in yearly meetings..." 

What Mary advised Edmund and his family to now do was just be quiet about the whole matter and "let things take their course." On her view, it would surely be bad for Edmund's sister to leave her brother as a result of family interventions. She says that if anything is done to separate them now, "there will be much less chance of his [eventually] marrying her." And it is that which Mary thinks everyone should understand to be the main goal now that a clandestine elopement has taken place.

Edmund is thunderstruck by all of this. For he has come to see that Mary can think only of what course of action will conduce to the highest level of future well-being and never considers what is morally appropriate. She is unable even to comprehend that there might be some right or wrong here, regardless of what would work out for the best.

Well, I am concerned that my own above-linked comments on van der Vossen's treatment of whether Socrates "should" have fled Athens as his friend Crito wished may be construed to reflect a Crawfordian blindness to the question of what action would be right--and not just prudential--for Socrates under the circumstances. For I, too, generally focus on what can be expected to be most beneficial for all parties. So I want to stress here that I do not deny the existence of moral truths. Nor am I a relativist--cultural or otherwise--on these matters. I understand the distinction that Austen is highlighting and agree wholeheartedly with her. Furthermore, I believe the distinction she makes is important, and even insist that many self-described moral skeptics are confused on this score.

But I do resemble morality deniers in being doubtful about our ability to know that this or that proposition counts as a moral truth. Because I am unlike Edmund and Fanny in failing to trust to religious foundations for ethics, and because moral claims seem to me to be unlike empirical assertions in having no likely foundation other than "intuitions" and prudential considerations, I am hesitant to place much confidence in any conclusions claimed to emanate from some alleged "moral sense." 

So, unlike Mary Crawford, I don't make prudential values to be either the "be-all" or "end-all" of value theory (and I include aesthetic values in this judgment). But I do think that we often have little else than humble prudential considerations to rely upon. As I have said elsewhere, I am comfortable putting prudential values at the kiddie table, but I have little faith in the pronouncements descending from the fancier place-settings--no matter how loudly and confidently they are declaimed. 


I therefore hope I can be excused for thinking that it's possible that Socrates ought to have given a bit less weight to Austenian arguments here and paid significantly more attention to the pleas of his friend Crito.