Friday, July 19, 2024

Can ANYTHING Be Done?

 



Naturally, many Americans are extremely concerned about the upcoming Presidential and Congressional elections. I include myself in this group. Even those who are seemingly safe under their beds have a lot to be worried about. 

But from my prone, dusty perspective, the recent Supreme Court decisions regarding Presidential Immunity and the regulatory authority of Executive agencies are much more concerning because they will remain in effect whoever wins in this election. Other less recent decisions have also made the country either explicitly much less democratic--like Citizen's United, or much less satisfied with the laws that intimately affect them--like Dobbs.

Are matters entirely hopeless? Given the current  provisions of our Constitution and the the current composition of the Court and the cultishness of one of our two major parties, it seems to me quite difficult not to answer this in the affirmative. One of these conditions could be altered by immediately "packing" the Court, but, presumably any such solution would be short-lived. It would surely be "unpacked" (and perhaps "repacked") by any Executive that doesn't like how it looks at any given time. And it seems to me that most of the Constitutional alterations that I have seen proposed over the last decade would do little given the current Supreme Court's willingness to interpret whatever turns up there in any fashion a certain Executive would prefer.

Would anything help, assuming for a moment there was actually time for it to be accomplished before the next election? Well, given the near impossibility of amending the U.S. Constitution, I'm afraid the answer is NO, no matter how much  time was available. But I can think of  some Constitutional provisions that, if, per impossibile, they could somehow be shoved into our outdated "founding document," would have amazing curative powers. 

The U.S. citizenry simply must have the power to recall Federal elective officials and reverse Supreme Court decisions. There should also be the possibility of Federal referendums. I'm not sure anything short of these admittedly huge alterations could provide much more than temporary symptomatic relief.

I wrote about these issues in some detail in my book (the amount of detail was partly a matter of what I now think was an error in my thinking about Reversal). Under our current dire circumstances, I will reproduce most of this material here. As I do this, I will point out (using braces { } and courier font) the mistakes I think I made in the book. This material is all from Chapter 9.



***********************

Recall, Reversal, and Referendum

While 19 U.S. states have provisions for the recall of state officials, it is doubtful that the recall of any Federal official is allowed by the Constitution. Where the term of office is two years or less, this makes sense. Recall elections are time-consuming and expensive—especially so for the individuals subject to them....

But a sensible term of, say, four to six years must always come with the possibility of recall by an unsatisfied electorate. And just as governors are subject to recall petitions in many states, the President of the U.S. must be removable, other than via impeachment. Trollope explains why:

We know that he can be impeached by the Representatives and expelled from his office by the verdict of the Senate; but this in fact does not amount to much. Responsibility of this nature is doubtless very necessary, and prevents ebullitions of tyranny such as those in which a sultan or an emperor may indulge; but it is not that responsibility which especially recommends itself to the minds of free men. So much of responsibility they take as a matter of course, as they do the air which they breathe. It would be nothing to us to know that Lord Palmerston could be impeached for robbing the treasury, or Lord Russell punished for selling us to Austria…. We are anxious to know, not in what way they may be impeached and beheaded for great crimes, but by what method they may be kept constantly straight in small matters… [T]hey must be…of one mind with the public. Let them be that; or if not they, then with as little delay as may be, some others in their place. That with us is the meaning of ministerial responsibility. To that responsibility all the cabinet is subject. But in the government of the United States there is no such responsibility. The President is placed at the head of the executive for four years, and while he there remains no man can question him… There are no reins, constitutional or unconstitutional, by which he can be restrained. He can absolutely repudiate a majority of both Houses, and refuse the passage of any act of Congress even though supported by those majorities. He can retain the services of ministers distasteful to the whole country. He can place his own myrmidons at the head of the army and navy, or can himself take the command immediately on his own shoulders. All this he can do, and there is no one that can question him. (1862, Vol. 2, Ch. 10)

And, Trollope adds with disdain, “Seeing that Mr. Buchanan has escaped any punishment for maladministration, no President need fear the anger of the people.” It is just such considerations as Trollope puts so well here that ought to make obvious that in Presidential systems too, a praiseworthy democracy requires the ability to recall all elected officials with terms greater than two years. State recall provisions vary, but I would recommend that a total of certified signatures equaling perhaps 25% of the number of voters in the last election for the office in question should be required to put the question on the ballot. A majority of those voting for recall in the recall election would prevail, but only if some minimum percentage of the electorate participates, perhaps 90% of the total number of those who voted in the election that put the individual in office. While such elections are indeed costly in many ways, democracy seems to me to require that recall of these officials be allowable at least once in any two-year period. Where any recall election is successful, a new election must be held as soon as possible.

Judicial “Independence” and “Separation of Powers”

It is interesting to note to what almost incredible extent the 18th Century constitution-builders in America amplified Montesquieu’s “separation of powers” trope into a principle that could be used to fuel the fear of any scent of “despotism.”[1] I will be discussing this matter in relation to bicameralism and the executive veto shortly, but it is important at present to distinguish what any parliamentary system shows to be largely a red herring, from the separate, and I think defensible, tenet of judicial independence. This matter is important here because the precept of independence must be made to harmonize with democratic principles when considering the selection of judges and the prospect of the revisability of their decisions by the people. Obviously, judges—particularly those who will sit on the highest courts—must have a specific sort of expertise. While this may be true of legislators as well, judges are not correctly viewed as our representatives. Where legislators will be chosen largely because of the concord between the voters’ views and what the candidates say they intend to do, judges—while also having political perspectives—clearly need to have legal expertise of a type that the electorate is unlikely to be in a position to assess. {And, unlike elected officials, they should not be subject to recall.} But...if, as I think, high judges must ...be selected by the executive, the legislature, or both, there should be no imputation of “separation of powers” here. Such “independence” as is required must be consistent with a judiciary that will remain responsive to the general will. As Paine pointed out, the distinction of government into Executive, Legislative and Judicial branches is more a distinction of words than of things.

The sort of responsiveness needed, even among the judiciary, seems impossible where judges are elected for life terms. And as Croly 1914 warns, a too-powerful judiciary makes us a nation not of laws but of lawyer-sovereignty—a country ruled almost entirely by unaccountable attorneys.[2] Selection of judges by the executive and confirmation by the legislature thus seem to me appropriate, but only if appointments are for fixed (perhaps) 12-year, though renewable, terms. Those judges wanting to remain on their benches at the end of their terms should be required to apply for continued service to the executive, who could either agree or dismiss them and make alternative choices, with such decisions again being subject to confirmation by the legislature.[3]

Judicial independence is, of course, more than a matter of selection and retention or dismissal of judges. There must be reasonable confidence, not only among members of the judiciary, but among contesting parties, that decisions will be made based on the merits of cases, rather than political considerations or estimates regarding whether some decision may be overturned by an executive or legislative edict—or even by the results of a popular plebiscite. But such judicial power must nevertheless not be itself used to entirely upend the will of the people. As Amy Gutmann 1993 points out, judicial review of legislative acts must go no farther than delegation of popular control, and not move on to the complete alienation of it.

There has been no end of disputes about this issue, not only in academic works, and in legislatures and courthouses around the country, but on battlefields of the Civil War. There are today numerous subjects where one can find the demos on one side and the courts on another. Gun control is a good example. But thorny as they are, I believe these issues are resolvable if we correctly distinguish among types of cases. State legislatures and executives have long been jealous of what they take to be the rights of their constituents to live as they please, and they have been quite willing to set aside criminal and civil cases and focus their objections to judicial power on those specific matters wherein a Federal judge strikes down or preempts a state law or constitutional provision based on an interpretation of the (U.S.) Constitution or a Federal law.[4] The distinction the states have tried to make here is on the right track but insufficiently careful. Justice Marshall was right concerning some matters. There ought not to be “second-guessing” of the Federal government or its high court by a state {or other litigant.} There must be a final say regarding what is the foundation (or at least the current basic structural law) of any nation, and, since elections are not truth-tracking, voters should not be used to weigh evidence or re-try cases. Neither, however, should the Federal courts be substituting their judgments for what the people...want..... Thus, it seems to me that there are some court decisions {or better: some aspects of all decisions} that ought to be reversible by popular vote.... 

Disgusted about the regular striking down by various courts of popular legislation involving such matters as child labor, workers’ compensation, and sanitary conditions in tenements, Theodore Roosevelt wrote,

It is the people, and not the judges, who are entitled to say what their constitution means, for the constitution is theirs, it belongs to them and not to their servants in office—any other theory is incompatible with the foundational principles of our government. If we, the people, choose to protect tenement-house dwellers in their homes, or women in sweat-shops and factories, or wage-earners in dangerous and unhealthy trades, or if we, the people, choose to define and regulate the conditions of corporate activity, it is for us, and not for our servants, to decide on the course we deem wise to follow. We cannot take any other position without admitting that we are less fit for self-government than the people of England, of Canada, of France, who possess and exercise this very power. (Roosevelt 1912)

Roosevelt’s solution was not to move to a parliamentary system, but to require that a certain subclass of judicial decisions be subject to overturn by votes for reversal. He wanted the courts to be independent, but believed that such independence was more at risk from corporate and legal special interest groups than it was from “popular tyranny.” He gives some minimum deliberative requirements for these actions (e.g., the plebiscite would have to wait at least two years from the election of the legislature that enacted the law that was struck down), but he isn’t quite clear on how to interpret the results of these votes. He writes, “It is a matter of mere terminology whether this is called a method of ‘construing’ or ‘applying’ the constitution, or ‘a quicker method of getting the constitution amended’” (1912). This is glib, I think: it is important for any democratic populace to be able to know what is in its constitution(s). Roosevelt was wrong to suggest that this doesn’t matter, but the difficulty he points up with his remark is not easily handled. Both the constitutions and the statutes of all the various states involve specific methods for amendment, and they may not include language regarding “amendment via court decision” due to alleged unconstitutionality. Let me here provide my own tentative suggestion for the availability of reversal votes...

{I omit much of what I proposed here because I now think I was mistaken to try to categorize decisions as reversible or non-reversible based on the subject matter of the case at issue. What I now believe should be outside the citizenry's purview is any effect on the litigants who brought the case on which the disputed opinion arose. So, for example, if the new Presidential Immunity decision were to be reversed  (as I believe it should be), such reversal should not subject former President Trump to prosecution for any prior "official acts," but would apply to every President (including him) subsequently. In other words, it's not the subject of the case, but the extent of its applicability that matters here. The principle of non-retroactivity must be maintained for the rule of law to remain intact. But I think the following proposed phraseology from my book is still relevant.} 

A vote to overturn a decision of any court...shall be construed as a remand to the court issuing the decision as well as to the [relevant] legislature and executive. Such remand shall include instructions that either (i) the court revise its view of the conflict within some specified period of time; (ii) (a) the court advise the relevant legislature regarding how to draft [a law] producing substantially the same result... and (b) the legislature and executive enact this statute within the same specified period; or (iii) the court provide constitutional amendments that would, in the unanimous opinion of the judges, handle [any alleged conflicts] and request that such amendments be placed on the [appropriate ballot(s] forthwith. Said instructions must be clear that if, by the date specified within them, there is in effect neither a policy tantamount to that desired by the voters nor an amendment to the constitution on the ballot that would allow such policy in the opinion of that court, then each member of the court who voted that the legislation be struck down as unconstitutional be forthwith removed from his or her office for cause, unless either two-thirds of the legislature in question indicate by open vote that they are opposed both to enactment of any such legislation or constitutional amendment, or the executive of that government agrees that it is his or her own responsibility that no bill has been enacted and no constitutional amendment has been placed on the ballot.

It is quite likely that others can come up with a less convoluted procedure, but the reasons for at least some complexity should be clear.[5] The judges may have been quite right that [a] new law conflicts with one or more constitutional provisions; the legislature might pass new laws according to the judicial recommendations and have them vetoed, or the executive might receive nothing to sign that would address the matter. It therefore may be hard to find duplicity or, if it is found, it may be difficult to parse it. But what should not be lost in these weeds is the necessity, as Roosevelt, Croly, Beard and a number of other progressives understood, that some method must always be available for the people to get what they want. In a democratic country, citizens cannot be left, as the American people are today, with so little recourse to change things, to have their way.

The Referendum

I have not spoken highly of the initiative petition, instead taking an attitude that may make my views seem undemocratic.[6] It is my view, however, that considerable expertise and diligent study are necessary to make good laws, and that those achievements are not generally dispersed throughout a broad populace. Furthermore, the initiative is, as already indicated, highly manipulable. But the referendum, which enables only the striking down of statutes or executive orders the electorate does not like, is markedly different, and, within strictly demarcated areas, must be available. Surely, on such matters as whether a country should go to war, the population at large must not be relegated to the position of ineffectual boosters or protesters. It is generally fairly easy for people to know that they don’t want this or that thing that has been thrust upon them. I believe the mechanism for overturn of a law should be similar to that suggested above for the recall of an elected official: there should be minimum numbers set for both signatures and Yea votes. And the demand for substitute action by the legislature or executive (though not instructions regarding precisely what it must be, which would turn the event into an initiative) could be required. The point is that spontaneous actions by legislators and executives must be subject to repeal by referendum—as long as the issues do not involve matters that are fundamental to democratic principles....

The voters know better than anybody else can what they want and don’t want. Their representatives are expected to be able to go some way in figuring out what to do with that information. But neither the voters nor their representatives may know whether such actions will be “good for the people.” That matter calls for special sorts of scientific expertise, as it is a function of what various courses of action can be expected to produce in terms of future attractive options and successful choices. Neither the general populace nor their representatives ought to be expected to be extremely proficient in that area of prognostication. It is not always easy to disentangle the wants both from the ways and from the expected and actual values of the results: there will be overlaps, gaps and disagreements.[7] But democracy should allow us to do the best we can. The availability of referendums ensures that neither representatives nor experts appointed by legislatures or executives can usurp the basic democratic right of the people to indicate what they don’t want—and have what is unacceptable removed where possible.

As noted above, it is reasonable to be concerned that a “majority veto” by the electorate at large could cost minorities gains that they might make in legislatures through logrolling or strategic contributions, because, while intensities matter in deliberative bodies, they do not play where we simply count heads.[8] But while a distilled populism intentionally ensures equal {treatment, protection, and even more than than equality suggests with respect to} voice to minorities, it should not be expected to provide strategies to achieve minority rule. The people at large must be convinced {of all matters not involving democratic principles}. Of course, it is not always possible to know that our representatives actually approve of some action or do so in light of their general agreement with us on the issues: it may be that they are lying or have been bought. Vigilance is crucial in the area of public corruption, and the opportunity and means to cure illegitimate encroachments must be in the voters’ arsenal. In a word, the Progressives of Teddy Roosevelt’s time were right about the gradual usurpation of the people’s power, even if their proposals need tweaking. Confusions and conflations (as well as the intentional smokescreens sent up by traditional liberals and conservatives) have managed to deprive U.S. citizens of real democracy since the country’s creation. Yes, equal protections must never be violated. Yes, the judiciary must be independent {with respect to certain matters}. No, we cannot allow tyranny—even by the people. But it is possible to have real democracy for all that.

 



Footnotes

[1] An excellent discussion of this metamorphosis can be found in Gordon Wood 1969. It is fascinating to discover that at the time of to the signing of the Articles of Confederation, many of the individual states were extremely democratic, providing limited terms for judges, broad impeachment processes, little in the way of executive vetoes of legislative actions. As J. Allen Smith (1907, Ch. 2) notes, “In this respect the early state constitutions anticipated much of the later development of the English government itself.” Smith attributed this radicalism to the fact that the checks and balances in the English system and in the colonies first established in America “resulted from the composite character of the English Constitution—its mixture of monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy.” When the democratic spirit grew in the new world, there (at first) seemed little reason to retain all the restraining mechanisms. And so the Articles, like the state constitutions, entirely omitted them.

[2] “No reverence for the law can guarantee political and social liberty to a body of democrats who confide their collective destiny to written formulas as expounded by a ruling body of lawyers. In practice each of these systems develops into a method of class government. The men to whom the enormous power is delegated will use it, in part at least, to perpetuate the system which is so beneficial to themselves.” (Croly 1914, 279) See also the careful demonstration of the unavoidable defects of judicial lawmaking and the consequent importance of legislative codification in Austin (1869 Lect. XXXIX).

[3] Dismissals and appointments should be considered separate actions, since the legislature ought to be able to overturn a dismissal, perhaps by a 3/5 vote as if it were a veto. Since I have criticized the use of super-majorities above, I should note here that I have no problem with them when they are used exclusively to overturn contrary (simple majority) actions by another legislative branch or the acts of an executive elected by the same (or roughly the same) electorate.

[4] See, e.g., Ransom 1912, Culp, 1929, and Beard, 1912.  This issue was a stalking horse for Teddy Roosevelt during his Progressive period.

[5] A simpler, if less radical approach, according to which legislatures may overturn certain types of judicial decisions has recently been suggested by Ganesh Sitaraman 2019.

[6] As already indicated, that is the response that I’d expect to be taken by Nadia Urbinati, given what she says in Democracy Disfigured. (Urbinati 2014) For a more favorable view of strictly “yes/no” plebiscitary arrangements, see Jeffrey Edward Green 2011. My own view, like Croly’s, falls somewhere in between.

[7] Urbinati 2014 is instructive on the nuances of what she calls the “diarchy” of decisions and opinions.

[8] See, e.g., Clark 1998.

****************

You will remember of course, that I said at the outset of this post that changes of the sort I seek are all but impossible. Simply hopeless. Matters are just too dire. I believe, nevertheless, that it is good to know what one ought to strive for. Mark Norris Lance reminded me the other day of this particularly fitting (and moving) quotation: 

“I wish it need not have happened in my time,” said Frodo.
“So do I,” said Gandalf, “and so do all who live to see such times. But that is not for them to decide. All we have to decide is what to do with the time that is given us.”

No comments:

Post a Comment