[T]he nature of Presidential power entitles a former President to absolute immunity from criminal prosecution for actions within his conclusive and preclusive constitutional authority. And he is entitled to at least presumptive immunity from prosecution for all his official acts.
There have been numerous objections to this holding in Trump v. United States. Indeed, lakes of both tears and ink have been spilled over it, and I can't deny that I have contributed my portion to these murky pools. In my first expression of dismay over this decision, I concentrated on a specific provision that entails that the holding is more extreme than many seemed to realize. These elaborative remarks were clearly inserted intentionally, as they shows up several times in Justice Roberts' opinion. But in spite of this problematic content it somehow escaped the notice not only of media pundits and legal scholars, but also of the dissenting Justices. At any rate, every summar of the decision I've seen gets this aspect wrong, and in that way mitigates its effects.
Today, however, I want to focus on a more basic matter, the question of what is thought to be so terrible about the the granting of immunity to those who have been elected President, regardless of either the plain text of the U.S. Constitution or any arguments regarding how its language should be interpreted. We have all heard that the U.S. is supposed to be a country of "laws, not men," and that in any such jurisdiction, "no person must ever be deemed to be above the law."
But...why not? In a democracy, shouldn't the citizens should be the final determinants of what is and is not to be allowed under their watch? If the electorate can be said to have in some sense made, or been the source of the criminal laws when they elected those who actually put pen to paper and enact those statutes, why cannot that electorate indicate a wish to exempt this or that individual from anymore all of them? Couldn't any such exemption--including complete immunity from prosecution--be thought of as a kind of reward for winning an election, just as a number of various enumerated powers are? Can't it then be reasonably claimed that such "people power" is all that Justice Roberts' decision has made crystal clear?
I believe the answers to these important questions can be put quite succinctly. In fact, I think that they were quite eloquently put around 250 years ago in a well-known and historically important pamphlet. But before getting to that work, it is worth looking checking if the (also fiery) Sotomayor dissent to Justice Roberts' majority decision answered these fundamental questions just as well.
Naturally, the dissent being a legal document, it is bound to pay close attention to Constitutional language and prior decisions as the bases for claiming the majority got things wrong. But for our present purposes we can just note that the strictly legal issues are (a) controversial and so not likely to be associated with widely convincing demonstrations; and (b) probably at least a partial function of the prior political leanings of the Justices. That is, it's hard to deny that an element of political loyalty may have been involved both among those who argued that Donald Trump absolutely must have broad immunity from prosecution, and among those who held that even if Presidential immunity were defensible in the abstract (a proposition they claim to doubt), giving it to Donald Trump must be a terrible mistake.
In such an environment, it is unsurprising that that numerous utility arguments were brought on behalf of the views pushed by both sides. For example, the Roberts contingent touched on the possibly undeserved burdens prosecutions could place on ex-Presidents, who would surely be hounded by constant suits, charges, media calls, and investigations--burdents that Trump had already had been forced to shoulder during his first term in office. Furthermore, the idea was put forward that, considering these psychic and financial costs likely to be thrust on ex-Presidents, who would to want to run for the U.S. Presidency? Shouldn't we expect the best candidates to look for other lines of work? And, of course, this cohort concluded that if only lesser candidates came to the surface, sooner or later, the entire nation would suffer.
What about the dissenting cohort? What sort of arguments--utility-focused or otherwise--did they bring? Justice Sotomayor spends considerable time on what she deems President Trump's "treasonous acts," seemingly defying anybody to find anything in the Constitution that can be thought to shield anybody from that sort of behavior. Here are ten of the acts she mentions (with all citations and internal quotations here excised):

- He "spread lies that there had been outcome-determinative fraud in the election and that he had actually won."
- He "pushed officials in certain states to ignore the popular vote; disenfranchise voters; dismiss legitimate electors; and ultimately cause the ascertainment of and voting by illegitimate electors in his favor."
- He (allegedly) "went so far as to threaten on state election official with criminal prosecution if he did not 'find' [sufficient votes to win that state].
- He (purportedly) "developed a plan to disrupt and displace the legitmate election certification process by organizing fraudulent slates of electors."
- He sought to use the Justice Department "to bolster his knowingly false claims of election fraud by initiating sham election crime investigations."
- He "falsely present[ed] the fraudulent electors as a valid alternative to the legitimate elctors."
- He "sought to persuade the Vice President to use his ceremonial role at the January 6 certification proceeding to fraudulently alter the election results."
- He (purportedly) "attempted to use a crowd of suppoters that he had gathered in Washington, D.C. to pressure the Vice President to fraudulently alter the election results."
- He "falsely claimed that, based on fraud, the Vice President could alter the outcome of the election results."
- He (allegedly) "delayed in taking any step to rein in the chaos he had unleashed [and] attempted to exploit the violence and chaos at the Capitol by pressuring lawmakers to delay the certification...and ultimately declare him the winner."
As at least many of the above-listed actions seem to Justice Sotomayor to have been obviously treasonous, she concludes that they cannot be protected under any sensible interpretation of the Constitution. And, of course, she believes that the effects on the well-being of American citizens--indeed the very future existence of the country--of allowing a traitor to rule without any fear of future punishment ought to be undeniable.
Again however, if we leave both uncertain Constitutional debates and future utility estimates aside, perhaps we can ask the more explicitly philosophical question of whether an electorate either can or even ought to make its executive (even a distinctly evil one) immune to all prosecution. After all, that seems to have been Hobbes' view of the matter. Readers here may remember his arguments to the effect that it was in the interest of people suffering in lawless conditions of nature to contract with a Leviathan who, subsequent to such agreement could not be coherently punished...or even safely criticized. On that view, even if a population insisting that consideration of future utilities favors bestowal of Presidential immunity are dead wrong, it is completely within their "constitutent authority" to grant that protection to their President/King/Monarch/Emperor/Poobah.
As I mentioned at the outset of this blog, however, the Hobbesian view was very effectively criticized by a not-quite-forgotten political philosopher who participated in the fervid constitution-making that occurred in France around time of its Revolution. In addition, this democrat somehow managed to keep hold of his head. I refer to the abbé Emanuel Joseph Sieyès.
Sieyès most famous pamphlet was the hugely influential What is the Third Estate? But just a month or two before publishing that diatribe, Sieyès put out his Essay on Privileges. It is notable that while Sieyès had no particular problem with the concept of monarchy in the abstract, on his conception, to be defensible, it needed to be understood to be a predominantly ceremonial office, something the people could use to identify and celebrate their homeland. He believed that it was perfectly fine to reward Kings, but they could not be endowed with any privileges (not even the power to veto legislation). He argued, in fact, that it makes no sense for the people use their inalienable "constituent power" to bestow privileges of any kind.
Well, why not? I will let Sieyès speak for himself:
The aim of law is to protect liberty and property, and to render easier the fulfilment of the great moral precept, from which all positive law proceeds,—do no harm to your neighbour.
What does Sieyès claim can be inferred from this first principle?
[If] there is one supreme law which ought to be the parent of all others, and that is,“Do wrong to no man.” [Then] it is this great natural law which the legislature distributes, as it were, piecemeal in applying the principle case by case to the various private orders in society.
[But] to be exempted from the action of any particular law is to be endowed with a right to harm one's neighbours.
Provided the law in question is good-- and such as are not should not exist--to have the exclusive right of doing anything [that conflicts with it, and is therefore] morally wrong is to rob one's neighbours of a part of their liberty.
All privileges then are, in the very nature of things, unjust, odious and opposed to the great end of all political society.
Every law, as we have already observed, expressly says, “Do wrong to no man.” Where then any class of citizens enjoys an exemption from any particular law, it is directly saying to those citizens, “You are permitted to do wrong.” There is no power on earth which should be authorised to make such a concession. If a law is good it ought to bind every individual; if bad it ought to be abolished. It is an assault upon liberty.
All privileges, then, from the very nature of things, are unjust, odious, and contrary to the supreme end of every political society.
Where then any class of citizens enjoys an exemption from any particular law, it is directly saying to those citizens, “You are permitted to do wrong.” There is no power on earth which should be authorised to make such a concession. If a law is good it ought to bind every individual; if bad it ought to be abolished. It is an assault upon liberty.
The entire body of citizens is the principal object. It is that which is served. Ought it then in any sense to be sacrificed to a servant who is only entitled to a reward for having rendered it a service?
But what about the additional power we give to our political leaders, or the other rewards bestowed upon them? Is that also an absurd, contemptible idea? Not at all:
Reward the member that has merited well of the body; but do not perpetrate the absurd folly of abasing the body before the member.
I should note that Sieyès does not ignore utility considerations in his pamphlet or elsewhere in his writings or speeches. But in discussing those expected results here, he concentrates on what any privilege similar to immunity from prosecution is sure to have on those on whom it is bestowed:
The professed intention of the privilege [may bave been to incite him to better actions, but it has succeeded only in depraving him.
His heart [will become] agitated with a desire of being first, with an insatiable thirst of domination. This desire, unfortunately too agreeable to human nature, is a true antisocial malady, and, from its very nature, it must always be detrimental. Judge then of its ravages, when opinion and the laws of a country conspire to lend it their power and support.
Thus sayeth Abbé Sieyès. I have to admit that this skeptical cleric seems to me a kindred
spirit. (Is this because of or in spite of his well-known character flaws? Hmmm. Quien sabe?) But Sieyès somehow managed to avoid the guillotine and live a long--if not
terribly happy--life. He reminds me, in fact, of another flawed and regularly derided revolutionary whom I also admire, Viktor Chernov. Both squandered what power or influence they ever managed to obtain. But, at least for part of their careers, each was a thoughtful and committed democrat. And they were both escape artists of the highest order: while one miraculously avoided the Jacobins' guillotine, the other somehow managed to outwit the Bolsheviks, their pick-axes and gulags. One hated his king the other his tsar, but neither was ready to replace his ruler with a dictatorship of either sans-culottes or proletariats.

To conclude (as I often do here at luckorcunning), let me urge a focus on finding that course of action which would be most authentically democratic under the circumstances. Such a move is often necessary not only to improve a polity but in some cases to keep it alive. And bestowing prosecutorial immunity to a current or past head of state is exactly the opposite of what is called for by democratic principles.